Divine command theory

Call their view the restricted moral view; call the view that all moral statuses are to be understood in voluntarist terms the unrestricted moral view. However, the implication of this response is that if God commanded that we inflict suffering on others for fun, then doing so would be morally right.

In this sense, autonomy is incompatible with Divine Command Theory, insofar as on the theory we do not impose the moral law upon ourselves.

However, two new problems now arise. Even if individually insufficient as justifications for adopting theological voluntarism, collectively they may suggest some desiderata for a moral view: Alston concludes that Divine Command Theory survives the first horn of the dilemma.

This was not an objection to the truth of divine command theory, but Wainwright believed it demonstrated that the theory should not be used to formulate assertions about the meaning of obligation.

But this is so only if one appeals to the very strong form of theological voluntarism on which all normative states of affairs depend on God's will. Here is the question: In response to this, Nielsen argues that we simply do not have evidence for the existence of God.

Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy. It could be that even if obligation most obviously requires this treatment, the points made earlier about the promise of theological voluntarism also extend to other moral notions, even if in a less pressing way.

Given that the moral law exists internal to God, in this sense, God is not subject to an external moral law, but rather is that moral law. The view just described is a version of normative theological voluntarism. One can affirm normative theological voluntarism or metaethical theological voluntarism while failing to affirm theism; atheists and agnostics can be theological voluntarists of either stripe.

Therefore, because God is immutable Malachi 3: A Worry for Divine-Command Meta-ethics. Audi, Robert and William Wainwright.

Divine Command Theory

Nielsen advances an argument for the claim that religion and morality are logically independent. Consider the act of making a promise. But the other option appears unproblematic enough.

For one might well explain the notion that God is good and account for the intelligibility of divine commands by appeal to normative notions that are nonmoral.

So the only hope for the supervenience formulation is to hold that God's commands are proper parts of moral obligations: That is, the claim that good supervenes on God is no more arbitrary than the claim that it supervenes on some Platonic principle. But these reasons, while suggestive, are rather generic: One might hold that there is a single supreme obligation, the obligation to obey God.

The divine command theorist can then claim that the mistake of Nielsen and other secular moralists is that they fail to see that only in God can we as human beings find ultimate and lasting happiness.

Alan Donagan argues against these conclusions. In his discussion of the omnipotence of God, Thomas Aquinas responds to this understanding of omnipotence, and argues that it is misguided.

Quinn illustrates and expands on this claim by examining scriptural stories in which God commands some action that apparently violates a previous divine command. So while there is a sense in which it is true that all that God intends must come to pass, this sense is that of consequent intending rather than antecedent intending.

Divine Command Theory

For those committed to the existence of objective moral truths, such truths seem to fit well within a theistic framework. On this view, moral obligations attach to all human beings, even those so saintly as to totally lack any tendency, in the ordinary sense of that term, to do other than what it is morally good to do.

For our purposes here, they come to the same thing: Historical and Contemporary Readings. If one held to such an ambitious version of theological voluntarism—if one were to hold, say, that a state of affairs is morally good because it is a state of affairs that God wishes to obtain for its own sake, and that a character trait is a moral virtue because it is a property that God wants one to have for its own sake, and that an action is morally obligatory because it is antecedently intended by God, and so forth—then obviously the gambit employed by the less ambitious theological voluntarist is unavailable.

On Divine Command Theory it is therefore rational to sacrifice my own well-being for the well-being of my children, my friends, and even complete strangers, because God approves of and even commands such acts of self-sacrifice. If a good God prohibits torture he does so because torture is intrinsicly wrong, not merely because he declares torture to be wrong by fiat.

In what follows, I will, following Wierenga, take Divine Command Theory to include the following claims: And it is nonnegotiable that S not involve moral obligation. If the institution of promise making is just, then Rawls argues that the principle of fairness applies.

There are also a number of biblical examples of God commanding acts that would otherwise be thought to be morally wrong, acts such as plundering the Egyptians [Exodus University of Notre Dame Press:.

Divine command theory is a metaethical theory, while utilitarianism is a normative theory. Utilitarians can hold, indeed many have held, divine command theory. For example, according to Encyclopædia Britannica's entry on utilitarianism "Another strand of Utilitarian thought took the.

The divine command theory (DCT) of ethics holds that an act is either moral or immoral solely because God either commands us to do it or prohibits us from doing it, respectively. On DCT the only thing that makes an act morally wrong is that God prohibits doing it, and all that it means to say that.

The name “divine command theory” can be used to refer to any one of a family of related ethical theories. What these theories have in common is that they take God’s will to be the foundation of ethics.

Different from the divine command theory, the "divine command theory of happiness" is a doctrine of positive psychology, which holds that happiness and rewards follow from obeying the commands of the divine.

Euthyphro dilemma. The Euthyphro dilemma is found in Plato's dialogue Euthyphro, in which Socrates asks Euthyphro, "is the pious (τὸ ὅσιον) loved by the gods because it is pious.

Divine Command Theory. Philosophers both past and present have sought to defend theories of ethics that are grounded in a theistic framework.

Roughly, Divine Command Theory is the view that morality is somehow dependent upon God, and that moral obligation consists in obedience to God’s allianceimmobilier39.com Command Theory includes the claim that morality is ultimately based on the. Chapter 8: ETHICS.

DIVINE COMMAND THEORY: Cases of Divine Commands: DIVINE COMMAND THEORY does not rest on scriptures. DIVINE COMMAND is DIVINE COMMAND. People claim that GOD has COMMANDED them to do X.

Therefore doing X is a morally good act. X can be ANY ACT AT ALL.

Divine command theory
Rated 4/5 based on 82 review
Divine command theory - New World Encyclopedia